Editorial Considerations
Before the Internet Era, it was the 17th century which witnessed an enormous
turn in scholarly communication, to wit the rise of learned journals,
pioneered by Proceedings and Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society of London (founded in 1662). In 1750 there were in Europe ten
scientific periodicals, ca. 1830 the number reached 300, ca. 1950 there was
100000, and this development according to the rule of exponential growth
should lead to a milion of titles by the end of this century. In this
dramatic overflow of information, the new easy method of generating journals
due to the network technology seems to be no solace, rather a factor to
aggravate the crisis.
On the other hand, ever more efficient information technologies provide
us with a hope of overcoming the crisis/ At the same time, the new enormous
communication facilities promise ever growing collaboration. The present
project, which is to combine features of an academic newsletter and of a
journal, is born from such a hope. The said combination is meant as follows.
EFEREEING is a vital ingredient in any research, but brain storming, a
behaviour deliberately exempt from criticism, is vital too. Electronic
publishing is ideal for the latter, but the former must retain its rank
and function as well.
If a text has been accepted in a journal or a conference of high
standing, then without refereeing it can be published in "Mathesis
Universalis". Purposes and admissibility of multiple publications are
discussed below in connexion with Copyright issues.
Recommendation by special referees, closest to high standards of
academic journalism, will be resorted to if need be. Provided referees'
agreement, their opinions will be available in the journal too.
OPYRIGHT, a thing that even in its established state has something
metaphysical about it (as has any immaterial commodity) becomes still more
intriguing when texts are being displayed without any institutional
protection. The institution of a publisher connects the appearance of a text
with a legal system, hence the rights of parties involved are fairly well
defined and capable of being executed. Those who produce their texts in the
network do not need technical assistance of a publisher, and thereby get
deprived of his legal assistance too. Sometimes they do not wish the latter
either, but those who do should be given the opportunity of having it.
This journal takes advantage of appropriate legal devices. It has got ISSN
to introduce the journal into the system of library information, and is
publihed by the subject registered as foundation under the
Polish law (in the Court for Warsaw called "Sad Gospodarczy", Register No.
1914), and by virtue of its Chapter is authorised to act as publisher. As for
the contributions to this journal, Copyright is reserved for the Foundation,
but the Editor is authorised and willing to impart it to any Contributor who
will wish so (then suitable information will be annexed to the paper in
question).
A special Copyright problem may arise when a text becomes embedded into
a greater whole - namely a hypertext - with a link produced by an anonymous
WWW operator. How this is related to author's rights? A context may exert
influence on the meaning of a newly included item, and there is no certainty
that such influence will be harmless in each case. There is no ready answer
to this question, but it can be looked for in the following considerations.
Some rules of proper conduct can be shaped by a set of precedents, and the
Editors of learned journals belong to those who should contribute to a
reasonable practice. For instance, it is stated in the preamble to this
journal that not only downloading for private use is permitted but also the
linking of its items with other information resources (without excepting
other journals). There is suggestion behind this that if such authorization
is not given or reasonably supposed, then the text owner should be asked to
agree to the link in question.
The present Editors intend to ask also for such linking permissions
which would allow to list a linked paper in the table of contents of this
journal on account of its relevance to the journal's concern. This can be
seen as a multiple publication, one - so to speak - real (in the original
resource), the other virtual (in this journal). Should we multiply
publications in this way? There can be good reasons for that. Let it be
noted that there are journals which are published both in hard copy and
electronically. This clear case of multiplying is well advised because of
different uses and addressees of either version.
A case not less convincing is that of interdisciplinary contributions.
If a paper contributes something both to domain A and B, it is reasonable to
publish it both in a journal concerned with A and in that concerned with B,
each addressed to another audience. Analogous reasons motivate the
publishing of a paper in various linguistic versions, each of them having
different receivers. However, such multiple publications should be agreed
among parties involved. In particular, the case of combining a hard copy
version with an electronic one may prove advantageous for both sides, since
a network publication, more likely to be found by those being interested
(owing to links and to search engines), advertises that in the traditional
journal; on the other hand, the process of refereeing, if done in the
latter, spares time and effort of the networking editors.
These are examples of technical and organizational problems faced by
such a pioneering enterprise as an electronic journal. To close this list of
examples with an important problem, let me mention the need of hard copies
to be stored in chosen libraries for documentation purposes. However, a
solution will need a time as libraries lack suitable regulations for this
kind of activity. Such technical matters having been hinted, it is in
order to comment on the objective and the subject of this journal, as
expressed in its title.
MATHESIS UNIVERSALIS is a term invented in the 17th century to stand for a
universal method of sciences patterned on the deductive method of
mathematics, but also for the unified science which would result from
applying this method. The latter meaning depends on how one conceives
mathematics -- a point at issue also in our times. For instance, when Alfred
Tarski in his Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of Deductive
Sciences (Ch.6) equals the methodology of deductive sciences with the
methodology of mathematics, this may mean that the whole of deductive
sciences is seen as identical with mathematics; should we have eg deductive
philosophy, it would belong to the so broadly construed mathematics.
Heinrich Scholz (in notes to his Muenster lectures in 1934) when
rendering this term in German as "generalisierte Mathematik", defines the
so named field as the whole of mathematizable disciplines ("ein Inbegriff
aller mathematisierbaren Wissenschaften"), including philosophy.
In either interpretation of the phrase "Mathesis Universalis" it is
assumed that mathematical methods should be broadly applied to empirical
domains. The meaning of this assumption is nicely exemplified by Newton's
masterpiece Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (1687)
handling empirical reality with a calculus; even if a calculus lacks
deductive ordering, it possesses an inborn aptitude for taking such a form.
What about applying a calculus to mental reality? The process of doing
that started with George Boole who mathematically treated laws of logic
called by him "laws of thought". Here let me ask the Reader about his
understanding of the phrase "laws of thought": whether should it mean norms
to be obeyed (as in jurisprudence) or a kind of natural laws? Does nature
consist of bodies and minds? If so, the former would be governed by laws
of physics, the latter by laws of logic and of some other calculi
(subjective probability, information theory, decision theory, etc).
The answer in the affirmative to the question stated above (italicized)
underlies the editorial policy of this journal. Yes, the mind belongs to
nature and can be studied with the help of mathematical methods. Thus
mathematics proves more universal than we are taught in secondary schools.
So much we realize since Boole, but our time is ripe for more penetrating
questions, concerning relationships between both kinds of law, as discussed,
eg, under the heading "Information Physics" (it can be exemplified by Tom
Stonier's Information and the Internal Structure of the Universe,
Springer, London etc 1990). To bring up the issue, let me use a statement
by Roger Penrose in his Shadows of the Mind. A Search for the Missing
Science of Consciousness (Vintage, London 1995), Section 4.1 ("The mind
and physical laws").
File put on WWW server 17-02-96. Modified 30-03-96.
Abridged in October 1997.
We - our bodies and our minds - are part of a universe that obeys immensely
subtle and broad-ranging mathematical laws. That our physical bodies are
precisely constrained by these laws has become an accepted part of the
modern scientific viewpoint. What about our minds?
That our minds are so constrained too, is the conjecture expressed by the
title Mathesis Universalis. According to this conjecture,
mathematics is universal, governing both kingdoms, Bodies and Minds, as well
as the third one - that of Abstract Entities (numbers, proofs, algorithms,
etc.). Moreover, they are not separate kingdoms but permeate each other, hence
there may occur deep interrelations between respective sets of laws. A study
of these interrelations is a task for the future science which deserves to be
called "Mathesis Universalis" - in the sense related to the respectable
tradition and, at the same time, involving substantially new ideas.