The dialogue includes Jan Wolenski's review of Witold Marciszewski's
Logic from a Rhetorical Point of View (de Gruyter, Berlin,
etc. 1994. Series "Foundations of Communication and Cognition". pp.
XVI+312).
Wolenski's text, originally published in Grazer
Philosophische Studien (1994, vol 48, p.243 ff.) is here segmented; each
segment, handling a particular theme, is marked with the initial "W", and
followed by the author's ("M") responses. The text has been slightly altered
to the extent required by the form of dialogue.
The dialogue contributes to the logic and intelligence issue, though in an indirect way. The question of how to make arguments more argumentative, i.e. more suggestive, persuasive, convincing, can be answered only then, when a thorough theory of efficient problem-solving is provided; and this amounts to providing a theory of intelligence. The relation of argumentation to problem-solving is that of inclusion: every argument is expected to solve a problem (though not every solution consists in giving arguments).
-- W: Let us consider some vital issues in the order of chapters.
The first, "On the Rhetorical Point of View", discusses historical fortunes
and misfortunes of rhetoric, and why this subject, flourishing in the
antiquity and the middle ages, became neglected in the post-Leibnizian
philosophy. It also gives reasons why rhetoric should revive in a close link
with logic, linguistics and cognitive science.
-- M: Thanks for so excellent summing up. Since the last point
may seem controversial, let me explain that what I call rhethoric is a
modern theory of argumentative communication, which can profit from
the history of relations between logic and the traditional rhetoric.
-- W: In Ch.II, "Mind-Philosophical Logic as a Theory of
Intelligence", you consider the mind-philosophical logic as a kind of
philosophical logic, so related to the philosophy of mind as deontic logic to
the legal philosophy and ethics or temporal logic to the philosophy of
time. Note that the analogy of the mind-philosophical logic and deontic or
temporal logic is not quite clear, because these kinds of logic are based on
explicit calculuses, whereas the mind-philosophical logic is rather a
composition of various topics which are not integrated by a formal theory.
-- M: The point requires clarification, indeed. I coined the term
"mind-philosophical logic" to render von Neumann's claim that "a new,
essentially logical theory is called for in order to understand
high-complication automata and, in particular, the central nervous system".
That such a logic would rule the mind too (not only the brain), follows from
the Leibnizian philosophy of mind. I continue to believe that such a field
of research is needed, but I do not insist any longer on those analogies
with deontic or temporal logic.
-- W: The same chapter contains the basic distinction of objectual and
symbolic reasoning which is very closely related to concepts of formal
reasoning and material reasoning. You claim that most ordinary reasonings
are objectual for their connections with special subject-matters and
situations. On the other hand, objectual reasonings can be represented or at
least approximated by symbolic reasonings after suitable additions.
-- M: Now I see the difference between objectual and symbolic reasoning
as a deeper one than I did previously. I appreciate the use of
logical calculi for studying objectual reasoning, but rather those which
succeeded in discovering some non-verbal acts in reasonings, as did, e.g.,
Beth's semantic tableaux. Thus, one does not put the conjunction sign
between sentence; instead, he makes a list of facts. Instead of using the
disjunction sign, one branches a reasoning. Instead of using the negation
sign, one rejects a proposition, and so on. This is an example of how the
progress of symbolic logic makes it closer to actual arguments.
-- W: Ch.III, "Formalized versus Intuitive Arguments, the Historical
Background", outlines a historical perspective for the distinction of
formalized and intuitive arguments. Let me stress the point that the book
discussed is full of very interesting historical remarks and details; this
chapter is a very impressive example of a good use of history in studies
which are basically systematic.
-- M: Thanks for your understanding of my methodological approach. This
is the approach of an evolutionist who believes that the current knowledge can
be best understood in the context of historical development.
-- W: Chapters IV-VI constitute a logical interlude. Their titles, namely,
"Towards the Logic of General Names", "The Truth-Functional Calculus and the
Ordinary Use of Connectives", and "The Predicate Calculus", hint at an outline
of logic which, according to you, provides a logical skeleton for rhetoric.
Although these chapters are not intended as a contribution to logical
theory, one can find in chapter IV an original treatment of the problem of
existential import of categorical sentences and their quantified
counterparts. A comparison of logical schemata with ordinary meanings of
logical particles is a very important feature of this part of the book.
-- M: The phrase "logical skeleton for rhetoric" requires a
comment, but I prefer to make it at the end of our discussion.
-- W: In the next two chapters (VII-VIII), entitled "Reasoning,
Logic, and Intelligence" and "Defining, Logic, and Intelligence", you offer
a general discussion of how logic is related to rhetoric. This discussion is
based on some results taken from cognitive psychology; in particular, you
accept the connectionist model of mind and its activity.
-- M: I understand your résumé as a request to explain my points more
clearly. In fact, I am not so eager to base them on cognitive psychology.
When referring to it, I try to explain my ideas in a context expected to be
familiar to prospective readers. Though these ideas go back to von Neumann,
they are far from being assimilated by logicians, semioticians, etc. Hence
my reference to views being more in vogue, and my insistence on case studies
to present less familiar notions in familiar examples. After such case
studies in the chapter "Symbolic Logic and Objectual Reasoning", there
follow those in the last chapter "Implicit Definitions and Conceptual
Networks". And this last is, in a sense, most important.
-- W: ?
-- W: What this all has to do with logic?
-- W: Hence, your project of rhetoric is cognitive in nature. You
even use the term "cognitive rhetoric" as a label for your own ideas as
well as similar conceptions. In general, cognitive rhetoric is distinguished
by an extensive use of logic in the description of arguments. In this
respect, you closely follow the Polish analytic pattern: logic controls all
human rational activities. Thus, cognitive rhetoric must be sharply
distinguished from Perelman's project on which rhetoric and logic are quite
different activities. On Perelman's account, rhetoric studies arguments
which are effective in persuasive actions, independently of their logical
correctness. Obviously, your vision of rhetoric is much more normative than
Perelman's is. By the way, it is a pity that you did not compare your ideas
with Perelman's views; as a matter of fact, Perelman is even not mentioned
in the book.
-- W: And what about the relation of cognitive rhetoric to that
postulated by Perelman?
-- W: My main objection concerns the concept of logic. Although
you mention twice that truth-preservation is a mark of formal logical
arguments, you, in my opinion, overlook that this a fundamental point when
relations of logic and rhetoric are discussed. Sooner or later, we must ask
whether there is a sort of rhetorical validity or correctness.
Unfortunately, I am not sure whether, on the view of yours, rhetorical
validity, if any, is reducible to logic or not. There is a real dilemma: if
rhetorical validity does not exceed logical correctness, it is too weak for
needs of rhetoric in its traditional understanding, but if rhetorical
validity is something more than truth-preservation by the form of arguments,
it is undefinable by logical means. This dilemma is well-illustrated by the
Golden Rule of Argumentation (p. 215): Show the things itself, that is a
universal and give it the most illuminating name you can find in the
language of your audience. Well, but what if the name is not "the most
illuminating"? Is the argument in question simply incorrect from the logical
point of view or improper for different extralogical reasons? And what is
role of logic in incorectness of arguments which is different from logical
invalidity?
-- W: Nevertheless, my suspicion is that you employ the label
"logic" in two various senses and that you sometimes shift from one to
another. Firstly, logic is a theory of correct (valid, truth-preserving)
arguments, and secondly, it is a theory which studies various devices useful
in arguments, for example, definitions, classifications, etc. It is
obvious that relations between logic and rhetoric look differently,
depending of which understanding of logic is employed. When you
distinguish objectual and symbolic reasonings, you probably think about
logic in its narrow meaning (logic as the theory of valid arguments), but
when you formulate the Golden Rule, the second concept of logic is taken
into account. This ambiguity is also present, when the concept of the
mind-philosophical logic is introduced.
-- W: Well, how do you see the relation between the "two logics"?
-- W: Let me add that your case studies, although very
interesting in themselves, do not justify the whole project as
logical, because they only show that an amount of logic is used
in arguments and logic can be used in their evaluation. Also
translating some arguments into MIZAR or other computer softwares
does not justify that the translated pattern is logical in the
strict sense; of course, I do not deny that such a translation is
important.
-- M: I assume that general connectionist point that the
concept of a thing is not likely to be represented in the brain by something
like a picture located at a definite spot. A concept, an image, etc. is
rather a functional totality resulting from a vast set of impulses
distributed to various places, and being synthetised by a data-processing
unit.
-- M: Look at what we logicians call a system of postulates, or an
implicit definitions. In such a system, the components of a concept are
distributed to particular postulates. True, these postulates are put down in
a spatial neibourghood, but in network a neibourghood means something
different, to wit the facility of quick communication. I claim that the whole
knowledge of an individual is like an axiomatic system as far as the way of
the defining of concepts is concerned, with the difference that for each
concept the set of relevant defining postulates has to be immense, and that
those quasi-axiomatic systems are not isolated from each other; instead,
they get dynamically connected by a gigantic number of impulses.
Nevertheless, implicit definitions as studied by logic provide us with an
excellent paradigm of knowledge representation and engineering.
-- M: I do like the idea that "logic controls all human rational
activities", but we have to consider the sense both of "logic" and "rational
activities". If logic is regarded as the most general theory of rational
activities, the statement is tautological. If logic is construed as
predicate logic, even with the host of its extensions, and non-classical
alternatives, then the statemnt is not true, since a lot of rational
acivities is controlled by intuitive arithmetic, for instance. I fancy ,
again following von Neumann's ideas, that a more extensive logic, taking
into account more subtle mechanisms than logical gates alone, does control
a good deal of human activities.
-- M: I agree with your suggestion that a mention of Perelman's
approach would better emphasize that of mine.
-- M: Note that my essay is not entitled "Rhetoric as Entirely
Founded in Logic". Instead, I ask how can symbolic logic (i.e., that taken
in the strictest sense) contribute to a better understanding of objectual
intuitive reasoning, as one most relevant to rhetorical applications (p. X).
Hence I do not pretend to introduce any generalized concept of validity,
like Descartes did not pretend to do when stating his "rules to guide the
mind". The Golden Rule as suggested by myself is just a rule of a proper
mental conduct. I agree that the phrase "most illuminating name" as used
there is not most illuminating by itself, but I hope the context sheds some
light on the question.
-- M: I endorse this distinction which belongs to the basic
vocabulary of people dealing with logic. What may be non-trivial, is how
people see the relation between, say, logic-one (which handles
truth-preserving data-processing) and logic-two (which studies devices
useful in arguments). It was Descartes and his followers who claimed that
logic-one is without any use for logic-two. Such an extreme attitude may not
appear nowadays, but when Ch. Perelman gives a book of him the title
"Logique juridique. Nouvelle rhetorique", and in that book we do not encounter
any mention of logical constants, etc., we find this use of the word "logic"
rather close to that praised by the old Cartesians.
-- M: I see logical calculi, i.e. logic-one, as a necessary tool for
logic-two. It has been said how the theory of axiomatic systems becomes a
paradigm of conceptual networks. The theory of normal definitions needs the
formalism of predicate logic. Furthermore, the basic way to inquire into
objectual reasoning consists in a contrastive study starting from symbolic
reasoning. And so on. Owing to a progress in preciseness, arguments become,
so to speak, more argumentative, and this is a contribution of logic-one,
via logic-two, into rhetoric. Thereby logic contributes to the theory
and to practical development of human intelligence, for most abilities
required for arguments are involved in any efficient problem-solving (being
the measure of intelligence).
-- M: This is exactly what I wish: to show that a considerable amount
of logic is needed for evaluating arguments, and for making them more
efficient, i.e. more argumentative. That I did not project any more is due
not so much to a virtue of modesty, but rather to a theoretical option
regarding the very nature of logic. There are two (at least) possible
options. According to one of them, logic is a hardware-independent system,
while according to the other, that von Neumann's (and mine), a system of
logic can apply to all the cognition and communication activities, only if
it proves adjusted to that hardware with which it is realized. Whereas such
a device-dependent system is required for rhetorical purposes, the current
symbolic logic does not meet the challenge. Nevertheless, it is the only
possible starting point in the way towards that future full-fledged logic,
expected to render all the kinds and subtleties of arguments which the humans
owe to their miraculous hardware.