|
 |
|
Dr. Mack is a professor of philosophy at Tulane University in New Orleans, Louisiana.
Occasionally one thinks that, perhaps because it has become so
tedious, multiculturalism has begun to pass from the scene.
Unfortunately, such thoughts seem entirely too optimistic in light of
the great extent to which multiculturalist slogans have become
culturally and institutionally ensconced, the great emotional and
financial stake that multiculturalists have in perpetuating their
visions, and the degree to which, usually under false pretenses,
multiculturalists are able to initiate new believers into their sect.
So it probably is still of some value to offer a dissection and
critique of the ideology of multiculturalism—a dissection and critique
that focuses on the rotten core rather than the surface that is
polished for marketing purposes.
Behind the mask of a benign celebration of diversity lies a deeply
corrosive rejection of all general norms, rules, or truths. This
rejection of general norms, both those dealing with knowledge and those
dealing with morals, derives from multiculturalism's insistence that
there are many essentially closed systems of perception, feeling,
thought, and evaluation—each associated with some racially, ethnically,
or sexually defined group. Thus, multiculturalism quite explicitly and
appropriately sees itself as rejecting the Enlightenment belief in
standards of reason, evidence, and objectivity, and principles of
justice and freedom that apply to all human beings.
Cultural Relativism
Multiculturalism is, in effect, a dressed up and politicized
version of cultural relativism—the doctrine that every group has its
own distinct but equally sound patterns of perception, thought, and
choice. According to cultural relativism, no one can validly object to
beliefs and actions of any group which reflect that group's own
indigenous worldview. While cultural relativists have always claimed to
be friends of tolerance—indeed the only true friends of tolerance—this
doctrine actually implies that no one can object to any group's
intolerance, if intolerance is that group's thing.
Neither the cultural relativist nor the multiculturalist can object to
Mayan infant sacrifice, or Spanish Inquisitional torture, or Nazi
genocide because each of these practices is validated by the
perspective within which it arises. To criticize indigenous intolerance
or any culturally authentic practice no matter how brutal or
exploitative, one must apply general, trans-cultural norms which both
cultural relativism and its multicultural descendent denounce as
imperialist. But multiculturalism's moral relativism precludes any such
appeal and, hence, it precludes any affirmative case for tolerance.
In addition to its moral relativism, multiculturalism also
proclaims (as the one great Objective Truth) that all truth,
objectivity, and evidence are also relative. Each culture has its own
truth, objectivity, and standards of reason and evidence. Thus,
whatever beliefs any culture emits, they are validated by the fact of
their emission. This, of course, precludes any rational dialogue among
individuals. Each individual is merely a representative of a certain
biologically defined perspective with its own idiosyncratic, but
self-validating, biases. Hence, each individual must agree with members
of his or her own group and be unable to make rational contact with
members of other groups.
By chanting his mantra of relativism, the multiculturalist can
evade honest confrontation with all intellectual challenges. Consider
the argument that multiculturalism cannot support tolerance since
grotesquely intolerant social orders can be as true to their
distinctive ways of perceiving, cognizing, and feeling, as any other
social order. According to the multiculturalist mantra, this argument
itself is merely an expression of one particular perspective, the
Eurocentric—hence, linear and logocentric mode of perception and
thought. Thus, this challenge, like all attempts at rational
disputation, can be rejected by anyone who doesn't feel that way about
it.
Tolerance
In contrast to the multiculturalist, the genuine advocate of
tolerance believes that, despite the profound differences among
individuals, there are some fundamental general norms—including
standards of rational discourse and norms that extend freedom and the
protection of justice to all persons in virtue of their common
humanity. Only such general norms provide a principled basis for
rejecting the suppression of disliked opinion, speech, religious
conviction, economic decisions, and so on. It is precisely to the
extent that we articulate and comply with such rules that each of us,
strange as we are to others and strange as many others are to us, are
able to live at peace, indeed, in fruitful mutual advantage with one
another.
Multiculturalism modifies cultural relativism in two important
ways. First, it ignores cultures as ordinarily understood and focuses
instead on biologically defined groups within
our society who may be recruited into political alliances based on
heightening their sense of alienation and victimization. Thus, as the
perceived political opportunities dictate, the multiculturalist focuses
on the supposed existence of sui generis Afrocentric, Female, Hispanic, Homosexual, and/or Native American modes of thought and feeling.
Multiculturalism is fundamentally anti-individualistic because it
expects each individual to conform in his or her perceptions, thoughts,
and assessments to those pronounced to be the authentic perceptions,
thoughts, and assessments of that individual's group. All genuine
blacks must share the Black perspective. All genuine women must share the enshrined Female perspective. All homosexuals must share the
Homosexual perspective—and so on. Your thoughts are either the
collectively constituted thoughts of your racial, ethnic, or sexual
group or they are thoughts insidiously imposed upon you by the dominant
White Male perspective. Group-think is the mark of authenticity.
Multicultural diversity both radically cleaves humanity into disparate
biological collectivities and radically homogenizes people within these
collectivities. For the multiculturalist, diversity is merely
superficial.
Multiculturalism's second modification of cultural relativism
consists in its expulsion of one supposed worldview—what
multiculturalism misidentifies
as the White Male perspective—from the Eden of equally sound worldviews.
All group perspectives are equal, but one is less equal than others.
The supposed reasoning on behalf of this expulsion is that the
so-called White Male worldview is uniquely guilty of commitment to
common objective norms of thought and action. Hence, it is said, this
rogue perspective uniquely stands in judgment of other worldviews,
subjecting them to its wickedly colonialist epistemic and moral
standards. Thus, this perspective—as befits its White, Male,
heterosexual roots—is uniquely totalizing, aggressive, and victimizing.
In reality, of course, what is being condemned by multiculturalism
is not some idiosyncratic White male, heterosexual perspective, but
rather the human enterprise of seeking, articulating, and employing
general norms that help us to distinguish between the true and the
false, the plausible and the implausible, the good and the evil, the
permissible and the impermissible.
The irony is that multiculturalism wants to hew to its own
judgments about the special defects of Western thought and the special
injustice and oppressiveness of the liberal Western social and economic
order while insisting that it cannot be expected to justify (or even
identify) the philosophical or empirical premises of its own judgments.
The excuse for this irresponsibility is the ritualistic claim that to
accept these demands for justification is to succumb to the Eurocentric
hegemony. Yet, at the same time, we are supposed to accept the truth of
the multiculturalists' historical and cultural analyses and the verity
of their all-embracing evaluations.
Multiculturalism presents us, then, with the spectacle of sweeping,
confident, and impassioned moral, historical, economic, sociological,
and aesthetic judgments and a simultaneous and often self-righteous
refusal to take any intellectual responsibility for any of those
judgments.
Was Hitler Evil?
In a campus debate a couple of years ago with an earnest
multiculturalist, I strove to help her see that she could not both
accept multiculturalism's relativism and continue confidently to
proclaim the profound evils of various regimes. In desperation, I
appealed to the instance of Hitler and Nazism. Given this relativism, I
asked her, can you even assert that Hitler was evil? Well, she said
after a moment of thought, I'm not valorizing him.
The primary purpose of multiculturalist educational proposals is to
instill in students and (increasingly) in employees and the population
at large the demonology that the apparently benign, tolerant, liberal
order is actually the most profoundly oppressive order ever to have
existed. People are to be initiated into the delights of victimhood.
They are to learn how to perceive themselves as victims (or
victimizers)—not of superficial wrongs like murder, mayhem, and
robbery—but of ever so subtle, exquisitely cunning, psycholinguistic
domination. It is psycholinguistic domination, i.e., the construction
of seductively hegemonic themes and discourses, that make the
derivative evils of racial or sexual exploitation possible (indeed,
inevitable). To recognize oneself as such a victim is to attain
multiculturalist enlightenment and, not inconveniently, an all-purpose
ticket for the increasingly lucrative multiculturalist gravy train.
Students especially are to be taught that arguments, doctrines,
works of art, or policy are never to be evaluated on their own merits.
For there is no such thing as the objective merit or demerit of an
argument, doctrine, work of art, or policy. Rather, these and all the
other products of the human mind are to be revealed as mere
valorizations of power. They are to be deconstructed to disclose their
inner character as instruments of repression—or, presumably in the case
of the privileged construction known as multiculturalism, as an
instrument of heroic resistance.
But is resistance objectively different from repression? Is
resistance objectively better than repression? These sly questions
might tempt the unwary multiculturalist back into the clutches of
Enlightenment discourse. But the well-versed multiculturalist can
recognize the serpent with her alluring offer of knowledge and can, as
his greatest act of resistance, doggedly close his mind.
Throughout the academy and eventually society at large, the
multiculturalist demands that the classification of people by race,
ethnicity, sex and/or sexual orientation be emphasized at every
possible opportunity. Individuals are not to be seen or judged as
individuals but as tokens of
this or that tribe or caste. Since no one from one tribe (with the
exception of white males) can be judged by members of any other tribe,
each racial, ethnic, or sexual group must be assigned its own homeland,
its own reservation within the university and within the worlds of
commerce (cf., set-asides) and government (cf., Lani Guinier).
Between the homelands comprising this new form of apartheid there
can be, if multiculturalism is correct, no rational discourse, no
rational evaluation, and perhaps not even mutual understanding. Given
the premises of multiculturalism, there cannot even be any rational
accommodation among the worldviews that are now supposed to be
strategically united in their struggle against the White Eurocentric
devil.
Multiculturalism is the esoteric form of virulent ethnic politics.
Remove what the multiculturalists describe as Male Eurocentric
dominance and what, in reality, is the residue of liberal tolerance and
belief in the efficacy of rational investigation and debate, and
multiculturalism will proceed to do for the liberal university and for
liberal society what ethnic politics has done for Yugoslavia. []
|
|
|
 |
|
|